Two Kinds of Ontological Commitment

1829 Words4 Pages

Participants in the debate about `ontological commitment' would benefit from distinguishing two different ways of understanding the notion. If the question at issue is `what is said to be' by a theory or `what a theory says there is', we are debating `explicit' commitment, while if we ask about the ontological costs or preconditions of the truth of a theory, we enquire into `implicit' commitment. I defend a conception of ontological commitment as implicit commitment; I also develop and defend an account of existentially quantified idioms in natural language which sees them as implicitly, but not explicitly, committing. Finally, I use the distinction between two kinds of ontological commitment to diagnose a flaw in a widely-used argument to the effect that existential quantification is not ontologically committing.

The question of ontological commitment is the question of `what a theory says there is'. So much is familiar to any student of Quine. See Quine, `On What There Is', repr. in his From a Logical Point of View (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1980), pp.1-19, especially p.15ff. Yet the theory of ontological commitment remains in poor shape, and we lack consensus even with regard to the most basic questions: how should we give precise formulation to the notion of ontological commitment, and should we treat existentially quantified idioms as ontologically committing? Without agreement on foundational issues such as these, ontology is an impossible discipline, for unless we understand which sentences in the language of our theory may be used in ways which are ontologically committing, we cannot know whether theories put forward by would-be ontologists have the ontological significance they want them to have. Indee...

... middle of paper ...

...in any sentences which make ontological claims about s but does say of some named objects that they are s. On some not unreasonable views of the semantics of the situation, Specifically, that sentences containing names are not existential quantifications in disguise, and that there can be no truth expressed by a sentence of the form `a is a ' where the name a fails to refer.

the theory cannot be true unless there are s, yet the theory does not contain any sentence like `There are s' which could count as an ontological claim about s. Although s are not among the explicit commitments of the theory, it is certainly the case that the theory is committed to s in some sense, for if the theory is true then s must exist, and anyone who endorses the theory yet does not believe that s exist deserves censure for failing to acknowledge the ontological cost of his theory.

Open Document